Lawyers
are trained to apply a set of reasoning tools to legal problems. These tools
include, but are not limited to, analogy and disanalogy, deductive syllogisms,
interpretive principles (cannons of construction), such as ordinary meaning
controls, specifically enumerated items limit general words to objects similar
to the specific words (ejusdem generis),
and ascribe to ambiguous words a meaning in accord with the rest of the
document (noscitur a sociis).
Legal theorists distinguish two
legal reasoning tasks. First, one must ascribe meaning to statutes, regulations
and cases. This task helps legal practitioners know or understand the official
rules. Second, one must identify a class of facts which fall within the rule’s
reach. This task helps legal practitioners understand or identify the scope of the
official rules. Lawyers, legal scholars, and judges generally employ their
legal reasoning toolkit to perform both tasks.
Lawyers employ other analytical tools
to assess legal problems. For example, grammar and logic rules play a role, as
do “practical-reason” tools. By “practical-reason,” I mean action-oriented
rationality, as opposed to what philosophers would call “pure reason,” which
concerns validity-oriented rationality, that is, reasons for accepting a
proposition as true or false, valid or invalid.
Lawyers must also keep abreast of
changes in statutes, regulations, and case law to adequately represent their clients.
This is the easy part, if only because each state bar requires a minimum number
of continuing legal education hours to maintain one’s license. But it is
equally important that legal practitioners keep their analytical skills sharp,
which means, in part, sharpening one’s practical-reason tools. In his recent
book, “Intuition Pumps and Other Tools for Thinking,” Daniel Dennett explicates
a number of practical-reason tools he personally employs in assessing philosophical arguments pertaining to consciousness and other mental states. Even though his focus is on these abstract philosophical inquiries, his tools may also assist lawyers.
Occam’s Cuts
Consider Occam’s Razor—a tool or
rule of thumb which posits that the simpler explanation is usually preferred
over a more complicated one. Occam’s Razor cautions that one should be suspicious
of complicated answers. But, as Dennett points out, one must remain alert to
over-simplistic answers, whose damning evidence lies in what is concealed or
omitted.
This leads Dennett to another tool,
a play on Occam’s Razor, which he labels “Occam’s Broom”: “the process in which
inconvenient facts are whisked under the rug by intellectually dishonest
champions of one theory or another.” Daniel C. Dennett, Intuition Pumps and Other
Tools for Thinking 38-41(W. W. Norton & Company 0213). Dennett calls
this an anti-thinking tool. He advises
one to focus closely on what is unstated.
Lawyers must master identifying what
is unstated. But that is only the first step. Once a lawyer identifies omitted facts
or omitted elements or principles to the underlying law at issue, the next step
is to identify whether the omission is doing any substantive work—Does its
inclusion significantly increase the chances that the opposite of what the
movant seeks will obtain? If so, exploit the omission to your client’s gain. If
not, do not rush into including what was omitted by the opposing party. Remember
Occam’s Razor—keep your side uncluttered and simple.
Beware
the Deepity
A personal favorite from Dennett’s
thinking tool repertoire is the “deepity.” “A deepity is a proposition that seems both important and true—and
profound—but that achieves this effect by being ambiguous. On one reading it is
manifestly false, but it would be earth-shaking if it were true; on the other
reading it is true but trivial.” Id. at
56-57. Deepities abound in legal petitions, motions, briefs, and even in case
law.
Consider this statement by Judge Richard
Posner from a famous case: “Law lags
science; it does not lead it.” Rosen v.
Ciba-Geigy Corp., 78 F.3d 316, 319 (7th Cir. 1996). On one reading, the statement
is false. Science, for one thing does not predate “law,” or at least not
obviously so. And, depending on what one considers “leading,” law leads science
insofar as scientific endeavors are limited by law in many ways. Historically,
in fact, under the auspices of law and authority, scientific endeavors have had
to yield to what the state or governing authority considered appropriate forms
of or matters for exploration, and even the appropriateness of scientific conclusions.
And, both federal and state laws often set limits on what can be tested (think
of endangered species, embryos, and humans) and how it can be tested. Federal
and state funds often underwrite scientific studies, studies which are
specifically selected for funding by these governmental bodies; to point out
the obvious, this selection process puts government in the position of deciding
which scientific endeavors advance and which do not, though the losers in this
selection process may still seek alternative funding.
Yet on another reading, whether law
lags science or vice-versa is a trivial matter considering the issue before the
court. As examples, consider two Texas Supreme Court cases which quote Judge
Posner. Both cases deal with the evidentiary burden needed to demonstrate
causation in chemical and toxic tort cases and both conclude, in part, that a
plaintiff can raise a jury question as to causation by introducing scientifically
reliable evidence—at least two epidemiological studies of a class of persons
similar to the plaintiff, under a set of conditions similar to plaintiff, which
show, with a 95% confidence interval, that the dose of exposure from a
defendant’s product doubled the risk of injury to the plaintiff. Bostic
v. Georgia-Pacific Corp., 439 S.W.3d 332, 340 (Tex. 2014); Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc. v. Havner,
953 S.W.2d 706, 728 (Tex. 1997). Neither case was deciding whether law leads
science or vice-versa. (Note, though, that the court in Bostic and Havner
accepted, if only implicitly, that the court, not the scientific community, at
least not directly, has the final say on what constitutes admissible scientific
evidence).
In neither of those Texas cases, nor
in Rosen, did the phrase—“Law lags
science; it does not lead it.”—do any substantive work other than, perhaps, its
utilization as an aphorism. But this aphorism alone has made its way into at least
sixty-one (61) cases across the United States. This latter fact reveals the
problem with deepities in motions, briefs, and cases: though without substance,
their simplicity and seeming aptness offer persuasive power which, if
unchecked, may override critical impulses.
Deepities, undoubtedly, may be far
more subtle than the above example. Sharpening ones practical-reason tools,
and, of course, legal reasoning tools, ensures clients the best defense and
prosecution. If you run across a deepity, blow it up! Point out what makes it
false, or conversely, what makes it trivial.
No comments:
Post a Comment