“The sober people of America are
weary of the fluctuating policy which has directed the public councils. They
have seen with regret and with indignation that sudden changes and legislative
interferences in cases affecting personal rights become jobs in the hands of
enterprising and influential speculators and snares to the more industrious and
less informed part of the community.”–James Madison, Federalist No. 44.
In
case any doubt to the contrary existed, Dan Patrick confirmed, by threat of
special legislative session, that bathroom integrity is among the most
important policy issues in Texas . . . at least for now. Aimed to combat the
threat of discomfort that genital-appropriate-students may experience by sharing
a bathroom with persons dissimilarly endowed, and the more speculative, and
easily controllable, threat of rogue perverts using gender identity as a voyeuristic
ploy, the Bathroom Bill promises bathroom integrity to genital-appropriate
males and females. For those non-genital-appropriate males and females, the bill
promises that they can find the nearest stand alone potty, including using a
teacher’s bathroom, to relieve themselves in quiet and solitary confinement.
Whatever
the Bathroom Bill proposes to gain in bathroom integrity or security, however,
it loses in human dignity and legal equality. On the integrity side, the bill
treats transgendered persons as outcasts, as opposed to human beings and
citizens entitled to the same dignity and respect afforded every other citizen.
On the security side, the bill does greater direct and certain harm to
transgendered students than it does protecting students generally. As for legal
equality, the bill targets transgendered students and banishes them from
traditional public school restrooms, which may constitute an unconstitutional
bill of attainder.
A. Bathroom
Integrity and Equal Dignity and Respect
Most people can identify or
sympathize with proponents of rules that clearly segregate restrooms according
to gender. There is a sense of comfort that comes with gender-segregated
restrooms for some people. This comfort may stem primarily from being
surrounded by what is familiar.
When it
comes to private establishments and private individuals, as opposed to
government buildings and public figures, the decision to accommodate patrons’
comfort might not sit well with transgendered patrons, and might even invite
rebuke. But the sting of being relegated to a separate restroom from all other
males and females can be met with an equal sting to the private establishment
by taking one’s business elsewhere. One could also stage a boycott of the
private establishment. Lost profits have a way of motivating a change in
policy.
When the
State, on the other hand, attempts to accommodate the comfort of one group of
citizens over another, with respect to restrooms, or anything else for that
matter, the sting of being relegated by law to a separate facility from all
other males and females cannot be matched against the government. One cannot
just take his or her business elsewhere. Sure, one might protest or boycott,
but unlike with private business, where lost profits motivate changed policies,
government does not experience lost profits, at least not in the same way as a
private business—private businesses cannot force people to purchase or use
their goods or services like government can. Further, even if one were to enlist
others to boycott the government, their efforts would prove futile unless they
first engaged in a life-long project of dismembering gerrymandered districts
and enacting public policies that combat political pathologies. Lastly, unlike
with a private business, a public pronouncement by the State that one group of
citizens is too different to join other males or females is an official stigma
upon transgendered students—one that will follow them throughout the State.
In Obergefell et al. v. Hodges, Director, Ohio
Department of Health, et al., the United States Supreme Court interpreted
the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to the United States
Constitution to extend the protection of certain fundamental liberties—“life,
liberty, and “property”—to “certain personal choices central to individual
dignity and autonomy, including intimate choices that define personal identity
and beliefs.” Throughout the opinion, Justice Kennedy intimately tied human
dignity to legal impositions. From the law of coverture—a legal doctrine that
treated a married, heterosexual couple as a single, male-centric entity—to
criminal laws against homosexual intimacy, Justice Kennedy submitted that the
legal stance toward women and homosexuals informed the way other citizens
viewed them, and how they (women and homosexuals) even viewed themselves, i.e.,
as something less than men, in the case of women, or less than everyone else,
in the case of homosexuals.
At
the heart of the Obergefell opinion
lies a compelling moral minimum owed by the State to each person within its
jurisdiction: every citizen is entitled to the same dignity and respect
afforded every other citizen by those who purport to govern them.
Pardon the Interruption (an aside)
Nothing
that has been said so far should be read to mean that no limits whatsoever could
be placed on what is commonly referred to as “identity politics.” Consider the
case of Rachel Dolezal, for example. After she was outed as a white-woman, she
announced that she identified as a black woman. Taking her identity seriously
may mean that others recognize her for who she is, which includes how she
identifies herself. But, does this mean that she should also benefit from
Affirmative Action policies that were designed to ameliorate the effects of
past injustices inflicted on black Americans? I think most people would answer
no, and not without good reason.
To answer
no, though, is to admit public limits to aspects of personal identification. The
question becomes, then, whether admitting any public limits to personal
identification also admits limits to the scope of one’s personal identity? If
dignity is tied, in part, to how one identifies his or herself, then one might
think government regulations which prohibit someone like Rachel Dolezal from
enjoying the full protections and benefits afforded other people with whom she
identifies in every respect would be an affront to her dignity and constitute
unequal treatment. Practical politics takes over at this point—a line must be
drawn in order to ensure Affirmative Action policies serve those persons whose
historical connection to systematic and pervasive discrimination has stunted or
stalled their economic, social, and political well being.
Though the
issue requires additional discussion and argumentation, which this blog alone
cannot facilitate, I submit that transgender-identity issues are different from
the Rachel Dolezal example in very significant ways. First, the reasons for
excluding Rachel Dolezal from taking advantage of Affirmative Action policies
center on historical political choices and actions which negatively impacted a
group of people. But the reasons for excluding transgendered persons from using
the restroom assigned to the gender with which they identify center on genetic
luck—being born with a penis or vagina. And, second, the need to preserve a
limited resource for the group for whom it was intended is not present with
bathrooms.
Before
moving on, I will leave you with this tougher example: What about Caitlyn
Jenner? Should a transgendered person who identifies as a female be able to
take advantage of public policies designed to ameliorate past discrimination
against women? The gender category of Women is race neutral and largely a
matter of genetic luck. If so, why? If not, why? How does this inform your
stance on the Bathroom Bill, if at all?
B. Bathroom Security and Personal Insecurity
Another
reason in support of the Bathroom Bill centered on bathroom security. Some
public officials preyed on public fear by suggesting that men might storm into
female-only restrooms to objectify or even rape women if transgendered persons
are allowed to use the gender-assigned restroom with which they identify.
There are
three (likely more) reasons why the security argument fails on its face. First,
the security issue does not address a problem with transgendered persons, but
with rogue perverts or criminals taking advantage of a restroom policy. Second,
and related to the first, to address the rogue pervert or criminal issue does
not require a law which prohibits transgendered persons from using certain
restrooms; in other words, there are less restrictive alternatives. Public
schools are well equipped to have procedural and security checks in place to
minimize the risk or threat of rogue perverts and criminals. Some such
procedural checks may include documentation from a transgendered student and
his or her parent with the student’s gender identification, coupled with other
documentary proof—medical or otherwise—so that school faculty and staff will be
able to identify those students who actually should and should not be in
certain restrooms.
Third, the
Legislature does not have enough statistical data or proof to demonstrate a
real risk to bathroom security by allowing transgendered students to use the
gender-assigned restroom with which they identify. We should be very wary about
allowing the Legislature to create a problem out of thin air, for fear that one
day that problem may be with you and you may have no recourse. This brings us
to the final issue.
C. Bills of Attainder
The
Bathroom Bill will likely be met with litigation. Most people should be or will
be familiar with the equal protection legal arguments that will arise (one such
argument was raised above in the Obergefell
discussion). The bill might also constitute an unconstitutional Bill of
Attainder, though the argument is not as direct as equal protection.
Article
1, sections 9 and 10, of the United States Constitution, prohibit federal and
state governments, respectively, from enacting bills of attainder. A bill of
attainder is an official rule that directs punishment of a particular person or
group. Alexander Hamilton best articulated the concerns addressed by the
prohibition against bills of attainder:
“Nothing is more common than for a
free people, in times of heat and violence, to gratify momentary passions by
letting into the government principles and precedents which afterwards prove
fatal to themselves. Of this kind is the doctrine of disqualification,
disfranchisement, and banishment by acts of the legislature. The dangerous
consequences of this power are manifest. If the legislature . . . may banish at
discretion all those whom particular circumstances render obnoxious, without
hearing or trial, no man can be safe, nor know when he may be the innocent
victim of a prevailing faction. The name of liberty applied to such a
government would be a mockery of common sense.”
The United
States Supreme Court interpreted the prohibition against bills of attainder to
apply to “legislative acts, no matter what their form, that apply either to
named individuals or to easily ascertainable members of a group in such a way
as to inflict punishment on them without a judicial trial.” United States v. Lovett, 328 U.S. 303,
315 (1946). The Court also broadly construes what constitutes “punishment”
within the prohibition’s parameters. As far back as 1810, the Court exclaimed
that a “bill of attainder may affect the life of an individual, or may
confiscate property, or may do both.” Fletcher
v. Peck, 10 U.S. 87, 138 (1810). More recently, the Court made clear that
punishment includes “imprisonment, banishment, and the punitive confiscation of
property by the sovereign” as well as “legislative enactment[s] barring
designated individuals or groups from participation in specified employments or
vocations, a mode of punishment commonly employed against those legislatively
banded as disloyal.” Nixon v.
Administrator of General Services, 433 U.S. 425, 474 (1977).
Now, the
legislation typically must identify a particular person or easily ascertainable
group. For example, in United States v.
Brown, 381 U.S. 437 (1965), the
Supreme Court held unconstitutional a law that prohibited Communist Party
members from serving as labor union officers or managers. The Court reasoned
that the law constituted a bill of attainder, as it identified specific
individuals, Communist Party members, and punished them by excluding them from
holding union positions.
But if the
legislation reads as a general prohibition that does not specify any
individual(s) or group, the question arises whether courts should look beyond
the words of the legislation to the underlying intent behind the bill. Courts
have shown themselves more and more willing to look beyond the text when it
comes to discriminatory intent.
So, is the
Bathroom Bill, once enacted, a bill of attainder? The bill is directed at “a
student who does not wish to use the facilities designated for use or commonly
used by persons of the student’s biological sex.” This language is likely
sufficient to demonstrate that it is directed to transgendered students
specifically. Even if neutrally read, there is enough legislative history,
courtesy of Dan Patrick and others, to show that the bill is directed at
transgendered students. And, the bill targets a specific subset (students who
do not wish to use the restroom that corresponds to his or her biological sex)
of a general group (students).
Will the
legislative act punish transgendered students? Broadly construing “punishment,”
the bill excludes transgendered students from using restrooms openly available
to all other students and relegates transgendered students to separate
facilities. This obviously negatively “affects the life” of transgendered
students, and excluding the student from designated student facilities on the
basis of the transgendered students’ identity may comfortably sit within the
definition of punishment for purposes of the prohibition against bills of
attainder.
Recall
that one of the underlying rationales behind the Bathroom Bill was to ensure
bathroom security. Taking this purpose seriously, the bill “punishes,” without
a trial, transgendered students for something that no transgendered student has
done. Criminal laws are already in place to punish any person, regardless of
race, gender, sexuality, religion, or political affiliation, who sexually assaults
another person. Should not those laws coupled with subsequent punishment
following a trial be sufficient to deter the conduct the Legislature purports
to be concerned with regarding the Bathroom Bill? Also, as argued above, there
are less restrictive alternatives available to public schools to minimize the
risks or threats raised by the Legislature.
Final Thoughts
Mindful
that there are no easy answers to many of the issues raised by the Bathroom
Bill, and certainly no answer that will satisfy everyone, everyone should at
minimum seriously question whether a statewide prohibition is the appropriate
response to a problem that, by all accounts, is largely hypothetical. Granted,
there are serious concerns raised by proponents of the Bathroom Bill that
cannot lightly be dismissed. The comfort and privacy concerns of female
students whose gender corresponds to their biological sex are valid concerns. And,
the normative stance and mores of a given community deserve respectful
attention. These concerns should be addressed by each particular school
district, because they are best equipped to address the specific concerns of
the local community and best equipped to address the needs of the students with
whom school faculty and staff have direct contact and intimate knowledge.
No comments:
Post a Comment